2 of 2

Richard Rorty: Critique of Representationalism, Opposition to Epistemological Method, and Edifying Philosophy

Learning Outcomes:

  1. Understand Richard Rorty’s critique of representationalism and how it shaped his overall philosophy.
  2. Analyze Rorty’s opposition to traditional epistemological methods and his redefinition of truth and knowledge.
  3. Explore the concept of edifying philosophy and its role in challenging the rigidity of analytic philosophy.

Overview of Richard Rorty’s Philosophical Perspective

Richard Rorty, a pivotal figure in contemporary postmodern philosophy, sought to redefine the nature of truth, knowledge, and language. His primary concern was how the Western philosophical tradition had mistakenly placed emphasis on representing the world accurately, a tendency he argued to be both misguided and irrelevant. This approach led to his critique of representationalism and epistemological methods. Furthermore, Rorty proposed an alternative, more pragmatic framework for philosophy, which he termed edifying philosophy. Each of these components are critical to understanding his influence on recent Western thought.


Critique of Representationalism

Rorty’s critique of representationalism forms the backbone of his philosophical departure from traditional epistemology. Representationalism, in broad terms, is the idea that knowledge is a mirror of reality, meaning that language and thought are designed to accurately represent the external world. Rorty rejected this premise on several levels.

  1. The Myth of Objective Knowledge:
    Rorty argued that the traditional pursuit of objective knowledge is based on a false assumption—the belief that human cognition and language can represent an external, mind-independent reality in a direct and faithful manner. He believed that there is no such thing as an objective “mirror of nature.” Instead, all knowledge is contingent and socially constructed. He advocated for a move away from the search for absolute truth to the recognition that truth is relative to particular historical and cultural contexts.

  2. Language as a Tool, Not a Mirror:
    Rorty redefined the role of language in philosophical discourse. Rather than viewing language as a medium that can accurately describe the world, he suggested that language is a tool used by humans to navigate their experiences. This pragmatic use of language is more akin to problem-solving than to accurately mirroring a pre-existing reality. He famously stated that truth is “what our peers will let us get away with saying,” which highlights his belief in the social and conversational nature of truth, rather than an objective correspondence.

  3. Dissolution of the Subject-Object Divide:
    In rejecting representationalism, Rorty also challenged the traditional subject-object distinction central to much of Western philosophy. He saw this divide as artificial and unhelpful for understanding human experience. For Rorty, the act of knowing does not involve a subject representing an external object accurately. Instead, it is a dynamic process of engaging with the world through linguistic and practical tools shaped by human communities.

  4. Rejecting Foundationalism:
    Representationalism often relies on foundationalism, the belief that knowledge must be built upon firm, unquestionable foundations (e.g., sensory data or self-evident truths). Rorty rejected this notion, arguing that no knowledge system can be grounded in absolute, neutral foundations. Instead, all knowledge is a web of beliefs, and each belief is justified only in relation to the others. This is aligned with holism and pragmatism, where the value of knowledge is not its correspondence to reality, but its utility in solving practical problems.

Important Note: Rorty’s rejection of representationalism did not mean he denied the reality of the external world. Rather, he denied that we could access or represent that reality in any final, objective manner.


Opposition to Epistemological Method

Rorty’s opposition to epistemological methods stemmed from his dissatisfaction with the analytic tradition of philosophy, which he believed was overly preoccupied with the nature of knowledge and justification. Rorty viewed traditional epistemology as an unnecessary and unproductive quest for certainty.

  1. Redefining Truth:
    Central to Rorty’s opposition was his redefinition of truth. He argued that truth is not an inherent property of statements that correspond to reality. Rather, truth is what works within a community of inquirers. Following Dewey and James, Rorty contended that truth is what is most useful or beneficial for achieving certain ends. It is a pragmatic concept, rooted in consensus and context, rather than in objective correspondence.

  2. Rejection of the Epistemological Turn:
    The epistemological turn in modern philosophy, from Descartes onward, focused on grounding human knowledge in secure foundations. Rorty viewed this turn as misguided. He believed that philosophy should not be concerned with providing a justification for knowledge but should instead focus on solving human problems. In this sense, Rorty sought to dethrone epistemology as the central concern of philosophy.

  3. Philosophy as Conversation, Not System:
    Rorty proposed a shift from the traditional systematic approach of epistemology toward a more conversational method. For him, philosophy should be understood as an ongoing conversation about language, culture, and society. Instead of seeking final answers or grounding principles, philosophers should contribute to a dialogue that helps humans understand their shared experiences. Philosophy, in this view, is not about finding the right method but about expanding the conversation.

  4. Fallibility and Anti-Essentialism:
    In opposing traditional epistemological concerns, Rorty embraced fallibilism—the idea that all beliefs are subject to revision. This leads to his anti-essentialism, where there is no fixed essence to truth, language, or reality. Instead of pursuing certainty, Rorty emphasized the contingency of knowledge and the historical evolution of human thought.


Edifying Philosophy

Rorty’s notion of edifying philosophy is key to understanding his positive project. Rather than constructing systems of thought or engaging in technical problem-solving, edifying philosophy aims to challenge and transform existing ways of thinking. It is a creative and disruptive force, designed to prevent philosophy from becoming stagnant or overly rigid.

  1. Philosophy as Redescription:
    One of the central aims of edifying philosophy is redescription. This involves finding new ways to describe our experiences and concepts in ways that are more fruitful or liberating. Rorty pointed out that philosophers like Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Wittgenstein were edifying philosophers because they sought to disrupt traditional thinking and offer fresh perspectives on selfhood, language, and truth.

  2. Anti-Systematic Approach:
    Edifying philosophy stands in opposition to systematic philosophy, which Rorty associated with analytic philosophy and the Platonic tradition. Systematic philosophy, according to Rorty, attempts to provide final answers to philosophical questions. In contrast, edifying philosophy is deliberately anti-authoritarian and non-dogmatic, resisting the temptation to provide closure to philosophical debates. Its purpose is not to resolve issues but to keep conversations open and dynamic.

  3. Ironism and Contingency:
    Edifying philosophy often leads to what Rorty calls ironism. An ironist is someone who recognizes the contingency of their own beliefs and is constantly willing to revise their positions in light of new vocabularies and perspectives. This contrasts with the metaphysical tradition, which seeks universal and timeless truths. For Rorty, the ironist embodies the pragmatic spirit by avoiding dogmatism and embracing flexibility in thinking.

  4. Philosophy’s Role in Culture:
    Finally, edifying philosophy contributes to cultural progress by transforming the way people think about themselves and their world. Rather than offering solutions to technical problems, it encourages self-reflection and imaginative thinking, promoting social and moral progress through creative dialogue.


Process Flow:
Conversation → Redescription → Expanded Perspectives → Cultural Transformation


MCQ:
Rorty’s critique of representationalism primarily challenges:

  1. The objectivity of sensory experience
  2. The belief that knowledge reflects reality accurately
  3. The existence of external reality
  4. The necessity of language in philosophy
    Correct Answer: 2


Home
Notes
Category
My Stuff
Search
Scroll to Top